Home
About How to Use
Taxonomy Glossary About the Author

The Existential Fallacy

Alias: The Fallacy of Existential Assumption1

Taxonomy: Logical Fallacy > Formal Fallacy > Quantificational Fallacy > The Existential Fallacy2

Form:

Any argument whose conclusion implies that a class has at least one member, but whose premisses do not so imply. Usually, this involves arguing from a universal premiss or premisses to a particular conclusion.

Example Counter-Example
All trespassers will be prosecuted. All unicorns are animals.
Therefore, some trespassers will be prosecuted. Therefore, some animals are unicorns.
Venn diagram

Venn Diagram:

This diagram represents both the Example and Counter-Example. The shading, which indicates the emptiness of a subclass, represents the truth of the premiss. The central overlap section would be nonempty if the conclusion were true, but the question mark indicates that it would be empty if the subject class as a whole is empty. Therefore, the diagram shows both arguments invalid since the premiss could be true while the conclusion is false.

Exposition:

A statement is said to have existential import3 if it implies that some class is not empty, that is, that there is at least one member of the class. For example:

Existential Import No Existential Import
There are black swans. There are no ghosts.

"There are black swans" implies that the class of black swans is not empty, whereas "There are no ghosts" implies that the class of ghosts is empty. To reason from premisses that lack existential import for a certain class to a conclusion that has it is to commit the Existential Fallacy.

History:

In the traditional formal logic of categorical syllogisms developed by Aristotle and subsequent logicians through the Middle Ages and up to the middle of the nineteenth century, it was assumed that the classes of things referred to by the subject and predicate terms of categorical propositions were non-empty. For this reason, certain arguments were considered valid that would not be valid if some class were empty: in particular, it was thought that an A-type proposition implied an I-type with the same subject and predicate terms, and an E-type implied an O-type, again with the same subject and predicate terms. This type of immediate inference was called "subalternation":

Subalternation4
All sapsuckers are woodpeckers. No boobies are titmice.
Therefore, some sapsuckers are woodpeckers. Therefore, some boobies are not titmice.

Subalternation is validating if the subject class of the premiss is non-empty, but not otherwise. For reasons explained in the Exposure, below, logicians of the later nineteenth century dropped the traditional assumption of non-emptiness, and adopted what is called the "Boolean interpretation"―after logician George Boole5―of universal quantifiers. Under the Boolean interpretation, I- and O-type propositions have existential import―see the Exposition, above―whereas both A- and E-types lack it. This has the consequence that some immediate inferences―such as subalternation―and categorical syllogisms which were valid under the traditional interpretation become instances of the existential fallacy.

Exposure:


Notes:

  1. Irving M. Copi & Carl Cohen, Introduction to Logic (11th edition, 2001), p. 207.
  2. Madsen Pirie, How to Win Every Argument: The Use and Abuse of Logic (2013).
  3. Brian Duignan, "Existential Import", Encyclopaedia Britannica, accessed: 6/11/2025.
  4. Thanks to Todd Cruzen for pointing out problems with the previous examples of subalternation.
  5. "George Boole", Encyclopaedia Britannica, accessed: 6/11/2025.
  6. "Ampliative Argument", The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, accessed: 6/11/2025.

Revised: 6/11/2025